Friday, May 12, 2017

10. For Philosophers only: Faith and Reason (20 pages)

Scotus’s Place in the History of Philosophy

July 14, 2008   

    In his Regensburg Address, Pope Benedict presented himself as the guardian of “the deposit of faith” and of “right reason”.  In so doing, he asserted authority over the past, present and future dialogue between two of the many strands in the western literary tradition, the Catholic theological tradition and the rationalist strand of the western philosophical tradition.
 
    To anyone other than committed Thomists, the Pope’s claim reveals a mind-boggling ignorance of the import of the Cartesian revolution, Hume’s empirical critique of the rationalist tradition, Nietzsche’s exposure of the will to power which propelled that tradition, twentieth century Existentialism, linguistic analysis and post-modernist re-readings of the dialogue among literature, philosophy and theology.

         (Scotus laid the literary foundations for the modern and contemporary critique of the supposition that inquiries governed by “reason” can yield definitive answers (i.e. answers that bring questioning to an end).  In his empirical approach, he also anticipated Wittgenstein’s insights into the workings of everyday languages.  In the Regensburg Address, the Pope does violence to Scotus and betrays an embarrassing ignorance of penetrating critiques of the supposition that a rigorous use of reason can yield a language which speaks for itself, timelessly and universally.  In effect, he advocates a “dogmatic philosophy” derived from an equally dogmatic theology.  And this ignorance matters, since he (and the Curial officials who impose his prejudices) use the language inherited from this sort of theologizing to silence dialogue concerning such questions as the ordination of women to the priesthood.)

    As a philosopher, I have been endlessly intrigued by the evolution of modern philosophy.  My dialogue with Hume, Kant, Rousseau, Hegel, Heidegger, Sartre and Derrida has convinced me that honest searchers must learn to “read the signs of the times,” listen to the cries of the marginalized and silenced, and discern the movement of the Spirit.  But a dogmatic theology grounded in an equally dogmatic philosophy fails on all these counts.  To expose these failures, I trace the synthesis advocated by the Pope to (1) the triumph of literacy over orality as the foundation of western culture, (2) the resulting illusion that languages function as virtual things-in-themselves, and (3) the added supposition that a Tradition confined to a dialogue among texts could ultimately generate a language capable of presenting the whole of reality transparently, in depth and detail.

   Nietzsche’s critique dramatized the interaction between orality and literacy by exposing the will to power enshrined in literary traditions governed by the totalizing thrust of language.  In texts which developed his re-reading of the western literary tradition, he forged two distinctive literary forms, the archeology of knowledge and the genealogy of morals.  As alternatives to the literary form of the autonomous text, these literary forms exposed the working of a will to power inherent (1) in the supposition that reason provides a detached, god-like perspective on the interplay among language, experience and reality and (2) in the supposition that analyses of everyday languages generated and governed by reason will yield a belief-system and a moral discourse which speak timelessly to all persons, regardless of the formative power of the prevailing culture.

    Today, the operation of such a will to power is obvious in the pronouncements of ecclesiastical authorities who assume that their a wedding of philosophy and theology legitimates judgments intended to “bind the future.”  Thankfully, there is an abundance of prophets who process everyday experiences in ways that falsify the implications of the constrictive belief-system they espouse.  But these prophets are not invited to enter the old-boys club.

    Sadly, most ecclesiastical authorities are unaware that they derive the linguistic formulations they seek to impose from a language which purportedly (1) has a life of its own and (2) presents reality transparently.  Pope Benedict’s stance on ecumenism offers a paradigm example.  Quite explicitly, he insists that the Catholic tradition is already in full possession of the truth.  On my part, I can only wish that he and the curial officials he has appointed were willing to recognize the lessons to be learned from the collapse of Communism.

    As a totalitarian belief-system, Communism functioned as a dogmatic philosophy which pretended to offer a transparent (and indeed scientific) vision on the whole of reality.  As a secular version of the eschatological themes in the Judaic-Christian Scriptures, it generated a moral discourse which justified the murder of millions and fostered self-deception among all who submitted to its reign of terror.  Harsh though my judgment may be, I do not hesitate to insist that attempts by the Curia to impose an imperial papacy have done the same sort of violence to individuals and that the temptation of Curial officials, Cardinals and Bishops to talk only to one another fosters the sort of self-deception which blinds them to unspeakable atrocities.

         (I suggest that the powers-that-be use a dogmatic philosophy to validate an entrenched form of life and legitimate their privileged positions in its hierarchical structure.  And as long as their self-deception remains impenetrable, they cannot imagine that Nietzsche’s dictum, “Nothing is true;  everything is permitted,” is an invitation to explore the call encoded in John, “Love one another as I have loved you.”

          (As a starting point, we do well to remember that Aristotle formulated his correspondence theory of truth at a time when languages generated by the Hellenic literary tradition had taken on lives their own.  Since he was well aware that languages in everyday use carved up reality in strikingly different ways, he attempted to forge a method of analyzing language and experience in a way that would yield a universal language which mirrored reality, without ambiguity, distortion or conventionality.  Over the course of centuries, this theory of truth (and knowledge) defined philosophical inquiry as a search for a language which mirrored, represented or presented the whole of reality precisely and comprehensively.  To bolster the pretense that they spoke with authority, rationalists embraced the supposition that a disembodied voice of reason provided a god-like perspective on language, experience and reality.)

    I suggest, therefore, that analyses of the import of the call to love one another as Jesus loves each of us must be framed by the hymn in the Prologue of John.  I also suggest that these analyses expose stark differences between the transcendentalism inherent in Benedict XVI’s embrace of Aquinas’s baptism of Aristotle’s hierarchically and teleologically structured conception of reality and Scotus’s search for a theological language capable of calling unique individuals to intensely personal involvements with Father, Jesus, the Holy Spirit and to equally unique individuals who entered his life.

    In the philosophical arena, there are three major points of divergence.  As a rigorous thinker, Scotus used reason as a tool in the analysis of language and experience, not a faculty which offered a detached perspective capable of demonstrating the existence of a rational and purposive God.  As an empiricist, he centered philosophical inquiries in moral rather than metaphysical issues.  And as a theologian inspired by Francis of Assisi’s intimate involvement with Jesus and profound respect for individuals, he sought to forge a language of discernment rather than a moral discourse designed to compel assent and consent to impersonal judgments on human motivation and behavior.

    From a contemporary perspective, therefore, Scotus’s critique of the contentious dialogue among medieval philosophers/theologians emerges as a recoil of reason upon itself.  I.e., the very structure of Aquinas’s Summa encoded a promise that analyses of traditional beliefs governed by reason would yield a comprehensive and closed system of clearly defined doctrines and a definitive moral discourse (the so-called natural law ethics).  But the validity of that promise rested on the assumption that an abstract conception of reason could generate judgments which imposed closure on questioning.  Scotus worked within the tradition, but used reason as a tool rather than a master to expose the constrictive nature of Aquinas’s belief-system.  And to find a god-term which escaped from the rule of the One at the core of Aquinas’s conception of reason, he centered his analysis of moral discourse in a language of love, with at least a rudimentary awareness that there can be no formula for love.

        (From an abstract perspective, the way that Aquinas’s use of reason generated this recoil of reason upon itself can be found in the texts of contemporary Thomists who pretend to speak from a detached, god-like perspective which all reasonable people can occupy interchangeably.  Since this perspective allows them to speak anonymously, it insulates them from the suggestion that their judgments reveal a massive self-deception.  As the postmodernist critique of the rationalist tradition shows, however, the pretense of closure generates the recoil inherent in the interiorized interrogatory stance of others who use reason as a tool to expose both the self-deception and the violence it legitimates.)

        (In this context, cursory readings of the decrees emanating from the Roman Curia reveal the debt of the judgments inscribed in these texts to the a theological discourse traceable to Aquinas.  Presumably, their anonymous judgments are validated by the authority acquired by Aquinas in the theological tradition they embrace.  To anyone willing to address questions which propel the postmodernist movement, however, judgments which silence the cries of the oppressed, dispossessed and marginalized and the protests of prophets who seek to formulate these cries as the cries of Jesus, a wounded Healer who shares their pain, anxieties and moral outrage, are little more than disguised exercises of a will to power.)

    The points of divergence between Aquinas and Scotus have far-reaching implications.  (1)  Aquinas assumed that the use of a conception of reason indebted to Plato and Aristotle would yield definitive doctrinal and moral judgments.  Presumably, since all human beings are rational animals, all could occupy the detached perspective offered by this abstract conception interchangeably.  And since this perspective presumably encompassed the whole of reality, the use of reason promised the comprehensive and closed belief-system consisting of clear and distinct doctrinal formulations inscribed in the Summa Theologica.  (2)  The application of the critical apparatus generated by the prevailing conception of reason to the closed belief-systems of his predecessors allowed Scotus to explore the interplay between an interiorized interrogatory stance (a stance which enabled unique individuals to voice moral protests against prevailing power-structures) and the totalizing thrust which promised definitive descriptive and moral judgments.  This approach found expression in his famous dictum, “In processu generationis humanae semper crevit notitia veritatis” (“In the process of human generations, the knowledge of truth constantly increases”).  And the approach itself is framed by an understanding that languages used to process experience are subject to constant revision.

    Despite his prowess as an empiricist and a logician, however, Scotus could not yet re-formulate the interplay between the metaphysical and methodological issues in medieval thought.  But his embrace of reason as a tool prepared the way for the privileging of an interiorized interrogatory stance in Descartes’s methodical doubt, the most dramatic instance of the recoil of reason upon itself in the history of philosophy.  Today, the Cartesian recoil finds its voice in the postmodernist hermeneutics of suspicion.  This hermeneutics uses reason as a tool to expose the deceptive ways that voices of authority clothe their judgments with Aristotle’s correspondence theory of truth, with its promise of an ideal language capable of presenting the whole of reality transparently, in depth and detail.

    Despite its limitations, therefore, Scotus’s entry into the rationalist tradition as an empiricist and logician led him to incorporate the interrogatory stance inherent in the interiorization of literacy in a metaphor which delineated the existence of unique individuals as a never-ending search for truth on a perpetual journey into the unknown.  And since he viewed this search as never-ending, he anticipated Heidegger’s use of the dictum, “Language reveals;  language conceals,” to argue that the dialogue among texts which constitutes the western literary tradition promised continual revelations of the meaning of Being, not judgments which imposed closure on questioning.

       (FN:  In ancient Greece, the detachment inherent in writing and reading was initially interiorized as an interrogatory stance.  As the literary tradition evolved, the so-called pre-Socratics sought to rescue a traditional participatory existence from the threat that the individualism implicit in an interrogatory stance would reduce dialogue to babble.  To that end, they centered their dialogue of text with text in a notion of “Being.”  Much later, Aristotle used this purportedly all-encompassing depiction of reality to frame his correspondence theory of truth.  In this context, he concluded that “reason” provided a detached perspective on language, experience and reality which would ultimately accredit a language which mirrored (or represented or presented transparently) the totality referred to as “Being.”

         Heidegger invoked the pre-Socratic notion of Being to assert his authority over both the rationalist strand in the philosophical tradition and Nietzsche’s re-reading of the dialogue among literature, philosophy and theology.  But he paid little attention to the critical apparatus which Nietzsche used to expose the will to power at the core of rationalism’s promise of a comprehensive and precise knowledge of a finite universe and every item in it.  As Kant realized, however, anyone who ignores Hume’s critique must suppose that the promise of certain knowledge absolves them from the need to answer questions concerning foundations.  And to this day, rationalists delight in finding flaws in the belief-systems of their opponents, but are blind to the ways that they rationalize flaws in their own rhetorics which are glaringly obvious to others.

          Over the course of centuries, the contention among Descartes, Kant and Hegel has been fruitful precisely because these rationalists sought to re-establish the rule of the One over the interrogatory stance which exposed the assumptions of their predecessors.  Hume’s empirical critique played a crucial role in this unfolding dialogue by showing that the rationalist strand in the philosophical tradition was dedicated to resolving metaphysical, moral, epistemological and methodological issues, not to generating testable implications.  And as long as philosophers, theologians and politicians play the role of ideologues, they insulate themselves from Nietzsche’s accusation that claims to authority over others are motivated by a will to power, not a search for truth, lest they be forced to acknowledge the arbitrariness, conventionality, self-deception and arrogance inherent in their claims to speak with authority on all possible issues.

            In this context, prophets who project metaphors designed to give voice to inarticulate cries of the oppressed and silenced have a different focus than scientists who formulate hypotheses designed to enable mute nature to give answers to well-formed questions.  But they, too, respect the way that an interiorized interrogatory stance can be used to subject the implications of descriptions of person-to-person involvements to the test of everyday experience.)

                        ---------

    An historian of science (A. J. Crombie) formulated the point at issue in a pregnant dictum:  “The way that a question is formulated determines to a large extent what will count as an answer and what will count as evidence for that answer.”  Historically, the conception of reason espoused by Benedict XVI subjected the interrogatory stance to the rule of the One because this move transformed the threat of endless questioning into fruitful inquiries. [sic]  Later, when this rule was personified as a detached, god-like perspective on the interplay among language, experience and reality which rational beings could occupy interchangeably, it promised objective knowledge and unbiased moral judgments.  And this rule is exemplified, again and again, in texts written by Pope Benedict which situate his critique of contemporary culture in a polar opposition between “absolute truths” and “moral absolutes,” on the one hand, and an unrestrained secularism, a moral relativity and a sterile subjectivity, on the other.

    To support this polar opposition, the Pope must ignore a critical apparatus which exposes both the historicity of literary formulations of foundational issues and the arbitrariness, conventionality or will to power inherent in questions framed by this polar opposition.  On its part, however, this apparatus can do little more than generate texts and utterances which speak in a hollow voice of prophetic protest.  For a moral discourse capable of delineating a realizable quest for a more fully human and uniquely personal existence, one must invoke Wittgenstein’s analysis of the workings of distinctive forms of life transmitted by everyday languages.

    To illustrate the point at issue, Wittgenstein invites one to draw a line and then be honest enough to acknowledge that a different line would mark a different distinction.  In this context, languages consisting of words laden with many meanings can be used in metaphorical formulations whose reach initially exceeds their grasp.  When these formulations are designed to transform a longing or aspiration into a realizable purpose, they generate testable implications.  If the metaphor succeeds, it introduces a distinctive purpose into the repertoire of purposes which are conducive to the quest for a more fully human and uniquely personal existence.  But there may come a time when drawing lines differently will yield more attractive purposes.

    Working from this insight, Wittgenstein put to rest the fear that words which did not encode clear and distinct definition or reference could be made to mean anything whatever.  To supplement the insight, he suggested (1) that words are like ropes woven from many strands, with no strand running all the way through and (2) that the meaning of a word was therefore its use in a form of life designed to realize a distinctive purpose.  (Note the difference between locating distinctions in purportedly precise meanings of words and in forms of life which remain alive in everyday language only as long as language-users seek to realize the purpose at their center.)

    To summarize the point at issue:  To counter rationalism’s promise of clear and distinct ideas in a consistent, coherent, comprehensive and closed system, Wittgenstein showed that everyday languages are not formal systems.  Instead, they are fertile mediums for drawing lines, for a purpose.  By implication, anyone who pretends to draw a definitive line must acknowledge the purpose they seek to promote, and they must therefore reveal why they seek to evoke a commitment on the part of others to that purpose.

    I suggest, therefore, that both postmodernist critics and followers of Aquinas are true offspring of rationalism and that Wittgenstein offers a far more fruitful critical apparatus for analyses of the relationships among language, experience and reality.  The weakness of rationalism lies its promise to replace everyday languages which carve up reality differently with a single comprehensive vision of the whole of reality.  (In effect, the lines inscribed in everyday languages as differences, forms or boundaries posit different distinctions and impose different boundaries.)  As a code for re-reading the western literary tradition, the hermeneutics of suspicion exposes this weakness.  In so doing, it protects the historicity of personal experiences from the impersonality inherent in the supposition that rational individuals can occupy a detached perspective interchangeably, and it erases the Cartesian distinction between subjectivity and objectivity.  But its dedication to subverting authority in any shape or form cannot support a moral discourse capable of processing experience in ways conducive to deepening person-to-person involvements.

    This moral discourse implies that intimacy as a realizable form of life invites unique individuals to co-author a shared journey into the unknown, and the language which enables them to transform the elusive longing for intimacy into a realizable quest promises that a deepening trust fostered by vulnerable and respectful interactions can be destroyed by suspicion in any shape or form.

        (Supplementary Aside:  The postmodernist critique of the centerpiece of the myth of Modernity, the conception of the autonomous individual, is succinctly encapsulated in an article by Roland Barthe which proclaims the death of the author.  This critique targets the appropriation of a theological formulation depicting the God of the Philosophers by authors of the myth of Modernity enamored with the ideals of the Enlightenment.  In its original version, the formula depicted a rational and purposive God who was the creator of the unique individuality of every human being, the master of the universe, the author of an ideal social order, the Lord of history and the arbiter of human destiny.  In the myth of Modernity, autonomous individuals create their own identities, use the discoveries of science to harness nature to their purposes, co-author ideal societies and thereby become lords of history and arbiters of their own destinies.  But in a straightforward application of the postmodernist subversion of the supposition that reason empowers individuals without pernicious consequences, Barthe concluded that texts of even the most creative authors in the western literary tradition were the product of a dialogue among texts and shaped by an imaginary audience.  And if even the most original authors could not speak in a genuinely personal voice in linguistic formulations consigned to writing, how could individuals hope to speak in their own voice in immediate interactions?

        In a rather obvious way, Barthe’s announcement of the “death of the author” echoed Nietzsche’s announcement of “the death of God.”  But neither Barthe nor Nietzsche address the question whether individuals who commit themselves to a quest for deepening intimacy can co-author a shared journey into the unknown.  In any equally obvious way, an analysis of the form of life derived from the metaphor of intimacy reveals that, to remain faithful to their initial commitment, individuals must allow experience to teach them that the longing for deepening person-to-person involvement calls them to vulnerable and respectful self-revelations in which they speak in their own voices, albeit it flawed ways.)

    In this context, Wittgenstein’s insistence that language consists of many forms of life, each designed to realize a distinctive purpose, poses a question for the polemical rhetorics of Thomists who accuse Scotus of undermining Aquinas’s magnificent synthesis of philosophy and theology.  With malice aforethought, I formulate the question as an accusation:  On some level, the violence they do to Scotus’s critique of his medieval predecessors bears witness to the need to deflect attention from the weaknesses of their philosophical and theological positions. 

(Pope Benedict’s Regensburg Address invokes a violent misreading of Scotus to support his embrace of Aquinas’s synthesis of philosophy and theology.) 

    Speaking for Scotus, I suggest that he would have willingly acknowledged a debt to Aquinas, though his immediate conversation-partner was Henry of Ghent.  But Aquinas assumed that theological reflections accredited by the conception of reason he espoused would justify a comprehensive and closed doctrinal system and definitive moral judgments, while Scotus formulated a critical apparatus which recovered the hollow center of the interrogatory stance at the core of the traditional conception of reason.  Many years later, Descartes would present this interrogatory stance as a methodical doubt capable of showing that the medieval synthesis of theology and philosophy was an edifice erected on sand.  And from a literary perspective, Descartes’ methodical doubt would have been inconceivable without Scotus’s empirical and logical critique of medieval rationalism.  But Scotus could never have subscribed to the myth of pure beginnings generated by the methodical doubt.

    On this point, Scotus anticipated Newman’s concern with the development of doctrine.  As an empiricist, he began in the middle, and as a theologian, he invoked the hymn in the Prologue of the Gospel of John to process his own experience in a way that allowed followers of Francis of Assisi to respond to the gospel call as Francis did.  As a result, he entered the contentious dialogue among medieval theologians/philosophers with a purpose that differed significantly from the purpose which led Aquinas to undertake the project of baptizing Aristotle.  First and foremost, at a time when others insisted that philosophical and theological inquiries were irreconcilable, Aquinas was determined to forge a synthesis which presented philosophy as the handmaid of theology.  Philosophers argued that philosophy promised universal knowledge.  To reduce philosophy to the status of a handmaiden of theology, Aquinas allowed a rationalistic conception of reason to govern the construction of his Summa Theologica.  In so doing, he fostered the illusion that the use of reason could compel universal consent to the theological system inscribed in that text.

    Decades later, when Scotus arrived at the University of Paris, academic discussions no longer revolved around questions concerning the relationship between philosophy and theology.  In this context, Scotus was free to begin his analyses of the received belief-system in the middle, and that beginning found expression in a pregnant dictum:  “In the procession of human generations the knowledge of truth always increases.”  (In processu generationis humanae semper crevit notitia veritatis.) 

    In short, Aquinas’s entry into the contentious dialogue among medieval academics was informed by his family’s embrace of a juridical form of life and shaped by the philosophical inquiries of Aristotle (and, to a lesser degree, Plato).  Scotus was indebted to an empirical tradition emerging in English Universities and to Francis of Assisi’s attempt to live the gospel message in a truly radical way.  As a result, his exploration of philosophical and theological issues addressed very different concerns that those enshrined in Aquinas’s Summa Theologica.

    On his part, Aquinas argued that a Summa which synthesized theology and philosophy could answer all possible questions and resolve all possible moral issues timelessly.  To support the argument, he accepted Aristotle’s categorization of human beings as rational animals without question.  On this issue, Scotus’s concern with the uniqueness of individuals involved him in an unsuccessful effort to formulate a conception of human reality which respected the mystery of human freedom.  To support these inquiries, he argued that an infinite God could not be bound by an objective moral order, even one that he had himself created.

    To focus the point at issue:  Following Aristotle, Aquinas privileged a conception of human nature which implies that, as rational animals, all human beings can occupy a detached, dispassionate, disinterested, god-like perspective on language, experience and reality.  Somehow, Scotus realized that this starting point could not generate a language capable of evoking the profound respect that Francis bestowed on every creature, great or small.  To that end, he introduced a dynamic interplay between will and intellect as the foundation for his introduction of haecceitas as a generative principle of unique individuality.

[Editor’s note: “haecceitas” is a term coined by Scotus which can be translated as “thisness. Every reality has a unique existence characterized by haecceitas.]

        (Supplementary Aside:  Today, the postmodernist deconstruction of rationalism’s literary foundations shows why no one can escape from the formative power of any language they wish to critique.  Scotus was no exception.  As a child of his age, he trusted “the natural light of reason.”  He did, however, subject the reigning conception of reason to a critical apparatus derived from an interplay between empiricism and logical analysis.  The results were a mixed bag.  On the one hand, in his desire to formulate a language capable of encoding Francis’s profound respect for the uniqueness of individuals, he challenged the privileging of universals which forced medieval theologians to address the question, “How are universals individuated?” from within.  To privilege individuality over the ruling conception of human nature, he grounded individuation in a generative principle of individuality called haecceitas.)

    From the perspective offered by the language which transforms the longing for intimacy into a realizable quest, Scotus’s use of haecceitas is a technical expedient designed to endow individuality with a positive value.  To place the dispute in its historical context, the answers of both Aquinas and Scotus to the question, “How are universals individuated?”, have the same structure.  Aquinas traces individuality to efficient causes which educe a human nature from this bit of matter, while Scotus traces it to a generative principle called haecceity.  But the theories offer divergent accounts of the process of individuation.  Aquinas locates the process of individuation outside the individual, while Scotus centers it within the individual.  Nonetheless, their descriptions of the process of individuation differ radically from the description generated by the metaphor of intimacy.  From the latter perspective, intensely personal interactions between unique individuals expose hidden depths in all concerned in a way that languages generated by metaphors of individuality cannot equal, and they alone plunge individuals into a process which enables them to learn how to speak in their own unique voices.

         (In the early decades of the twentieth century, Heidegger echoed Scotus’s haecceitas in his use of Dasein as the hollow center of a search for an authentically human stance toward Sein.  Presumably, this hollow center freed him from the formative power of reigning conceptions of human nature, including Kant’s conception of the autonomous individual.  From this starting point, he proceeded to fill the hollow center with his delineation of human existence as a quest for the meaning of Being.)
     
    Consequently, I center my critique of Scotus in the narrative structure of the literary form forged by authors who used stories to process Israel’s historical experience and the metaphors of intimacy projected by Israel’s prophets.  Medieval theologians lacked a theory of literary criticism capable of exposing the crucial roles played by this distinctive literary form and the metaphors it framed in the emergence of a language capable of presenting the quest for deepening intimacy as a realizable project.  Today, the insights into the workings of this narrative structure provided by biblical scholarship can be used to expose the way that philosophical and theological issues govern the Scriptural interpretations inscribed in the texts of Medieval authors. 

    In the most obvious instance, the meta-narrative which depicted the Incarnation as a response to Adam’s sin rested on readings which interpreted the story of Adam and Eve as an historical account of how God had acted in the past.  As a child of his age, Scotus could not break completely with the prevailing interpretative code.  As his insistence that moral issues involved discerning the activity of an incomprehensible God in the lives of unique individuals indicates, however, his critique of the Aristotelian metaphysical system baptized by Aquinas was an abortive effort to replace inquiries structured by the rule of reason with the narrative structure forged by Hebrew storytellers.         

 (NB:  Elsewhere, I argue that the meta-narrative which depicts the Incarnation as a response to sin is grounded in two events, a sin of Adam which supposedly severed the natural relationship between Creator and creatures and the crucifixion of the incarnate Word which offered fitting reparation to divine justice for Adam’s transgression.  Logically, this meta-narrative implies that, in and through the crucifixion, the saving (or justifying) activity of God was somehow complete, and this implication generated an immense variety of theories designed to show how the effects of the crucifixion are to be applied to Adam’s offspring throughout the ages.  Aquinas’s Summa presented one such theory.  Note well, however, that his belief that the use of reason could yield precisely formulated doctrines in a comprehensive and closed belief-system was logically dependent on a meta-narrative which centered salvation in a clearly demarcated event.

          (In marked contrast, the meta-narrative which frames Scotus’s incarnational theology ascribes the Incarnation to an over-flowing love which seeks intimacy with all human beings.  Since a journey to deepening intimacy is a process rather than an event, any written account of the shared journey requires a narrative structure which, in turn, guarantees that the workings of God’s activity in the lives of individuals unfold unpredictably in a never-ending story.

           (On a personal note:  In my fifty years as a priest, I have often met one-on-one with individuals who were going through the “dark valley.”  Some were suicidal; others were filled with rage;  still others were experiencing excruciating emotional pain;  still others were despairing or depressed;  and still others experienced an aching loneliness.  In each instance, I did not know how God’s (saving) love would touch them, but I was called to walk through the valley of death with them, without judgments or agendas.  To do that, I had to relive our meetings with the Father, Jesus and the Holy Spirit in intensely personal ways.  And this involved coming to each of them with my own pain, anger, fear, loneliness, and depression, listening in silence, and trusting that what I was to say would be given to me.

           (Through these experiences, I have become convinced that we sin because we are wounded, not because we are wicked.  As a result, I wonder why traditional definitions of God’s saving or justifying activity seldom call individuals to living encounters with Jesus, the Wounded Healer.)

    To belabor the point at issue, Pope Benedict assumes that the conception of reason baptized in his Regensburg Address promises that analyses of language and experience governed by a principle of logical identity validate the closed belief-system he espouses.  This assumption explains why he must offer a caricature of Scotus’s voluntarism.  The caricature distracts attention from the fact that an incarnational theology indebted to Scotus is centered in a narrative structure forged through centuries of a highly literary dialogue among ancient Hebrew storytellers.

    As I argue at length in the chapter on the story of Adam and Eve in my Christian Ethics:  an Ethics of Intimacy, the foundational stories in the Hebrew narrative tradition are centered in intensely personal interactions between an incomprehensible God and memorably unique individuals endowed with unfathomable depths and a mysterious freedom.  In this vein, Scotus sought a language which would enable unique individuals to discern the intensely personal involvement of a infinite God who is love in the everyday events of their lives.  Like Aquinas and other medieval philosophers/theologians, however, he lacked an understanding of the workings of the narrative structure of a distinctive literary form, the prose narrative, and this lack limited his ability to forge a language capable of sorting out tangled longings, passions, desires, motives and aspirations.

    Nonetheless, Scotus’s insistence that an infinite God could not be bound by an objective morality marked a significant departure from the traditional supposition that the opposite of absolute truths is a moral relativity or narcissistic subjectivity.  If anything, his incarnational theology yielded analyses of interactions between and among unique individuals which reveal the sterility of his use of haecceitas as an individuating principle at the core of a common nature shared by humans.

    In the final analysis, therefore, Scotus forged a distinctive philosophical framework designed to accommodate the incarnational theology he derived from a careful reading of the hymn in the Prologue of the Gospel of John.  This hymn framed the evangelist’s original reflections on the ways that God was active in human history in and through Jesus.  The opening verses of the hymn, “In the beginning was the Word, and the Word was with God, and the Word was God, and by and through him were all things made. . . .” place the eternal Word at the center of the act of creation.  Then, to lay bare the dynamics of the unfolding story of creation, a later passage attributes the entry of the Word into human history to an out-pouring of divine love.  And in a still later reflection inspired by this passage, the reformulation of the Second Great Commandment as a call, “Love one another as I have loved you,” describes the saving activity of the Word Incarnate as an all-inclusive love and a passionate longing to be intimately involved in the lives of all.

    Looking back, I see now the theological discourse that I received in the seminary was decidedly Thomistic.  As I sought to live with intellectual and personal integrity in my involvements with others, however, I discovered that judgments generated by supposedly objective moral principles did not enable me to discern God’s activity in anyone’s life, including my own.  In effect, I learned that there is no formula for love and that I often substituted appeals to authority for a prayerful listening to the Holy Spirit urging me to be compassionately present to wounded individuals, without judgments or agendas.  And when I subjected my judgments and agendas to analysis, I realized that I endowed a literary construct (a purportedly god-like voice of reason) with the power to govern my responses to God and to others.

    Today, I am saddened by the ingenious ways that followers of Aquinas interweave themes, metaphors, symbols and conceptions from the philosophical and biblical traditions to bolster his theology of transcendence.  But they are merely following the example of Aquinas who wove an uncritical categorization of human beings as rational animals (1) into his reading of the biblical passage which proclaimed that human beings were made in the image of the Creator and (2) into the hermeneutical code he derived from the medieval metaphor of the Two Books, the Book of Nature and the Book of Salvation-history.  In the Summa, he then supplemented the thesis that God’s moral will could be read off the Book of Nature by “a natural light of reason” with a philosophical argument which traced the teleological structure of Aristotelian metaphysics to a rational and purposive Creator who inscribed his moral will in a Book of Nature and the Scriptural passage which asserted that humans are made in the image of a rational and purposive God.

    I suggest, then, that Aquinas laid the literary foundations for the Protestant supposition that the Scriptures can be read as an autonomous text, self-interpreting and self-referential.   Ironically, to support the rejection of the theory of evolution, Fundamentalists who claim to read the Scriptures literally must also utilize a code from the Aristotelian belief in the fixity of species.)

    Though Thomists seldom acknowledge the fact, their embrace of a natural law theory derived from an objective moral order is still dependent on Aquinas’s supposition that “a natural light of reason” can show that the universe and every item in it has a teleological structure.  But the assumption is credible if, and only if reason is a natural endowment, Nature is a teleologically structured Book authored by a rational and purposive Creator, and a fixity of species prevails in that natural order.  As postmodernist archeologies of knowledge show, however, the conception of reason espoused by Aquinas is a literary construct, not “a natural light”  And as Descartes’ geometrization of the universe shows, the conception of a hierarchically and teleologically structured universe is a historical curiosity.  Finally, one must choose between a belief in the fixity of species and a theory of evolution which is bolstered by a wealth of evidence.  On these three counts, I can only wonder how anyone would seriously maintain that a rational and purposive Creator inscribed a “natural law” designed to fulfill his moral will in an autonomous Book of Nature.

    Simply stated, postmodernist archeologies of knowledge which expose the literary origins of rationalism reveal the will to power at work in judgments which pretend to impose closure on questioning, silence protests, or devalue the inarticulate cries of the oppressed, marginalized and outcasts.  Consequently, the only way that anyone who pretends to speak with authority can show the purity of their motives and the absence of hidden agendas is to show, beyond question, that their judgments are not motivated by (1) a desire to maintain a privileged position in the status quo, (2) a fear lest everything revert to a primordial chaos or the war of all against all depicted so vividly by Hobbes, (3) a willful determination to ignore Hume’s empirical critique of rationalism, and, in Heideggerian terms, (4) a determined effort to escape from the historicity of experience.  And even this would not suffice to justify the claim that they have access to a moral discourse grounded outside of human reality (in the will of God inscribed in a changeless natural order or in an eschatological vision of the course of human history).

    Returning to my personal history:  I left the seminary as a Thomist in theology, but a Scotist in philosophy.  And I did not become fully aware of the tension between the two positions until I underwent an in-depth exposure to Hume, Nietzsche and the Logical Positivists.  In his usual provocative way, Nietzsche suggested that the scientific tradition was propelled by a will to ignorance rather than a will to knowledge.  To support that challenge, he echoed the central point in Hume’s empirical critique of rationalism:  Since every item in the universe interacts with every other item, even experiments designed to test prevailing theories and hypotheses must ignore conditions which cannot as yet be identified or controlled in order to master those which can.  In marked contrast, Logical Positivists presented their version of the scientific method as the path to certain knowledge. 
    
    If a choice between Nietzsche and Logical Positivism, on the one hand, and Thomism on the other, were the only alternatives, I would have had to choose Nietzsche and Logical Positivism.  However, since Allan Wolter, OFM, introduced me to the history of western philosophy, I was aware that he, almost single-handedly, had inserted Scotus into the emerging dialogue among Catholic philosophers in the United States, and the influence of Scotus’s empiricism was evident in his fascination with the philosophy of science.  (Years later, his brother, Martin Wolter, O.F.M. proudly proclaimed that Allan had acquired an international audience of dozens.)  Through him, I was able to see that Scotus used reason as a useful tool, but refused to submit to its promise to compel assent and consent to a closed belief-system.

    For a time, the discovery that Logical Positivism was a prescriptive rather than descriptive definition of the scientific method led me to question the supposition that the scientific method could produce what it promised.  I was not yet ready to admit that Nietzsche had exposed the workings of a hidden will to power in the rationalist strand in the western philosophical tradition.  But I could not help but see that Husserl’s phenomenological method, though centered in self-consciousness rather than empirical data, rests on the assumption introduced by Descartes’ methodical doubt.  In effect, it promised that metaphysical, epistemological, methodological, moral and literary connotations could be stripped away by a method which revealed pure data of consciousness rather than bare empirical data.

    On another level, the centrality accorded to self-consciousness in Husserl’s approach shifted the focus from “teleology,” a belief that nature was ordered to a final end, to a fascination with the “intentionality of consciousness.”  And while I find a structured consciousness far more fruitful than a teleologically structured nature order, I must work from a metaphor of intimacy which implies that human beings are passionate, linguistic, imaginative and purposive beings who long for an ever more fully human and uniquely personal existence.  From this perspective, questions of purpose are more foundational than questions of intention.

        (In his break with Husserl, Heidegger developed a hermeneutical theory designed to read the western literary tradition as the vehicle for the revelation of the meaning of a creatively active Being.  For the god-term which lent coherence to this theory, he invoked the formulation of the notion of “Being” found in a literary dialogue in which later pre-Socratics played off the texts of their predecessors.  And since this dialogue occurred prior to the emergency of significant distinctions among language, experience and reality in the Hellenic literary tradition, it provided a richly contextual notion which allowed Heidegger to counter the detached existence privileged by Descartes’s methodical doubt with a participative sense of existence.  To exploit this context, he noted a simple fact:  When we seek to express anything whatever, we search for words and for linguistic formulations in the language at hand.  The conclusion:  (1)  The romantic supposition that unique individuals formulate original insights into poetic expressions of the felt experience of being human is pretentious.  (2)  An open responsiveness to Being is the sign of an authentically human existence.  (3)  Such a stance reveals that Being is creative and that language is the vehicle for the revelation of the meaning of Being.

        (Though I found Heidegger’s desire to articulate ways of being human in the twentieth century plausible, my suspicion of his hermeneutical theory persisted.  I could agree with the way that it incorporated the structure inscribed in the biblical story in which words spoken by Yahweh sent Abram forth on a journey into the unknown, but not with the way that it reduced language to a vehicle for the revelation of the meaning of Being.

        (Moreover, I gradually became aware that the way Sartre used this structure differed radically from the use made by Husserl and Heidegger.  Thus, in Being and Nothingness, Sartre appropriated the intentional structure of consciousness supposedly laid bare by Husserl’s phenomenological method for a clearly defined purpose.  This text is a tightly woven argument designed to trace the existence of unique individuals to an eruptive self-consciousness which plunges unique individuals into a perpetual journey into the unknown.  And since Sartre’s phenomenological analysis purportedly revealed the workings of a double nihilation at the center of the intentional structure of consciousness, it marked an intriguing return to the empty literary space projected by the Babylonian epics. 

        (In the end, though, Sartre replaced both Nietzsche and Heidegger as the main protagonist in my search for intellectual integrity because of his claim that passionate involvements between unique individuals inexorably degenerated into sado-masochistic interactions.  The reason is obvious to me now.  In Being and Nothingness, Sartre used themes and conceptions formulated by Descartes, Kant, Hegel, Nietzsche, Husserl and Heidegger to assert his authority over the rationalist tradition and over analyses of person-to-person involvements.  If his analysis were true, love would be an impossible passion, and my urgent longing for intimacy would reveal the absurdity of human existence.

         (Quite the opposite happened.  An excruciatingly painful mid-life crisis forced me to realize that my understanding of the dynamics of passionate involvements was indebted to Scotus’s incarnational theology, while my understanding of Scotus’s use of reason challenged me to mine the metaphor of intimacy for testable implications which would falsify Sartre’s theses.  And that realization was brought to the surface once again by my recent reaction to Pope Benedict’s Regensburg Address.  As I wrestled with the violence of my reaction, I discovered that the Pope’s misreading of Scotus’s role in the western literary tradition enabled me to see the ways that Scotus undermined the rule of reason which was so essential to Pope Benedict’s pretense that he was merely the spokesperson for a rational and purposive Creator.  To maintain his pretense, he had to deprive Scotus of any authority within the tradition, and he did so shamelessly.

         (In the reading of Pope Benedict’s Regensburg Address which emerged, I was led to wonder how the grounds he invoked to justify his commitment to an objective morality would be reconciled with the philosophical grounds invoked by Pope John Paul II to justify the same commitment.  Again and again, Pope John Paul II situated his moral judgments in a Personalism which presumably spoke as the voice of the intentional structure of an eruptive self-consciousness.  In this philosophical context, he replaced Aristotle’s teleologically structured natural order with Husserl’s intentionally structured consciousness.  But this replacement merely disguised the will to power inherent in any promise of certain knowledge, and clear and distinct ideas which offered a comprehensive vision of the whole of reality.

        (Lest this Aside go on forever, I refer any reader who has further questions to the reflections in which I bear witness to my understanding of the workings of the Sacraments and of my role in the institutional Church.  Here, I hope to limit myself to a succinct formulation of the point at issue.  The meta-narrative which presents the Incarnation as a response to the sin of Adam depends on troublesome definitions of justice and mercy.  In my relationship with God, I have often come before God in the words of the Publican, “God, be merciful to me, a sinner.”  Now, however, I come to Jesus as the wounded Healer.  Since I am profoundly aware that the problem lies in my inability to let each of the three divine Persons be intimately involved in my life, I cannot come as a humble suppliant awaiting some dramatic intervention on their part.  I can only be honest about the pain, fears, anger and shame that distorts my involvements with others, as I listen for a word of love which evokes responses which bring new life in God’s love and the love of other wounded individuals.

        (One further remark.  Regarding the issues which still separate the Catholic and Protestant traditions, those who perpetuate the polemics accept a meta-narrative which (1) insists that God’s justice had to demand fitting reparation for the sin of Adam, (2) celebrates a divine mercy which urged the eternal Word to become incarnate in order to make such reparation by a cruel death on the Cross, and (3) thereby perpetuates the dispute which revolves around a distinction between faith and works.  It is hardly surprising, therefore, that neither tradition fostered a spirituality based on an emphasis on the healing power of the touch of divine love in events in everyday life.  Here, I simply suggest that this failure suffices to show that the distinction between faith and works generates a misplaced debate.  The debate ought to be centered in differences between a conception of God derived from a metaphor of power and judgment and a conception of God derived from a metaphor of intimacy.)