Theorists in the ethical tradition share
the assumption that reason functions as a detached, disinterested, god-like
perspective on language, experience and reality. Implicitly, they assume that a literary
construct functions as an arena in which critics attempt to forge a second
level language about language capable of accrediting definitive judgments on
all possible moral issues. On its part,
the arena defines moral issues as responses to the dictum, "Might makes
right" and to the cultural relativity of moral notions. And it promises that a theory which satisfies
the criteria dictated by this conception of reason will triumph over all contending
theories.
Historically, the ethical theories which
are still locked in contention attract adherents because they probe a
distinctive dimension of human existence in depth and detail. To justify the closure on questioning
implicit in any judgment, however, they must ground moral discourse outside of
human reality or in some limited conception of human reality. (E.g., the will of God, the voice of reason,
the autonomous individual, the inexorable march of history.) Taken seriously, they are therefore
dehumanizing and depersonalizing.
Nonetheless, they have enriched the
understanding of the workings of moral discourse immeasurably. Consequently, in Christian Ethics: An Ethics of
Intimacy, I went to considerable lengths to show how theories which
explored five dimensions of human existence enriched the ethics of
intimacy. Thus, through an ethical
theory which focused empirical analyses of moral notions on the issue of
character, Aristotle illuminated the hard fact that our actions are formative
of the sort of person we become, regardless of our intentions. Centuries later, Hobbes and Locke used
naturalistic conventions forged by Aristotle to center their diverging
conceptions of a purportedly primordial social contract in a theory which reduced
human motivation to a natural desire for pleasure and for the avoidance of
pain, with reason as the only escape from a perpetual war of all against
all. To replace the authority of
political theories indebted to Hobbes and Locke with their own social concerns,
Utilitarians focused instead on the social consequences of actions. Then, to reject Utilitarianism in any shape or
form, Kant used Hume's empirical critique of rationalism to argue that we can
never know with certainty either the short-term or long-term consequences of
actions. In place of consequences, he
focused exclusively on intention. (In
his Critique of the Metaphysics of Morals,
the only valid moral intention is a willingness to do one's duty as that duty
is defined by a categorical imperative one dictates to oneself.) Then, in the twentieth century, Sartre both
utilized and subverted Kant's conception of the autonomous individual in an
analysis of a formless, unbounded consciousness which ensured that, in every
conscious experience, individuals are confronted with a potentially infinite
number of possible actions (responses) to whatever is presented in a contingent
datum of consciousness.
When I mapped this inter-textual dialogue
onto the form of life which transforms the longing for intimacy into a
realizable quest, I found that each of these theories illuminates moral issues
in potentially fruitful ways. But I also
found that those who use a particular theory to rationalize their moral judgments
clothe a hidden will to power in a narrowly focused theory generated by the
rule of reason.
I continue to hope that academic
inhabitants of the ethical tradition will begin to appreciate the postmodernist
insight that tangled moral issues lie, inextricably, at the core of every human
action and assertion. If they do, they
will see, starkly, that their use of reason as a detached, god-like perspective
on the human quest generates rhetorics which rationalize the rule of a
power-that-be.
Since I analyze moral discourse from the
perspective offered by Wittgenstein's analysis of everyday languages, I revise
the metaphor which led philosopher in ancient Greece to privilege the political
over the personal dimensions of experience.
This metaphor envisioned the city as the cradle and crucible of both
culture and civilization. My revision
envisions everyday language as the cradle and crucible of moral discourse. First and foremost, this language transmits a
form of life which enables language-users to transform a longing for intimacy
into a realizable quest. The
realizability of the quest is attested by all the tests which the implications
of the metaphor of intimacy successful passed.
But everyday English also transmits forms of life indebted to the
analyses of language and experience generated by the metaphor of power and
judgment, and these forms of life also enable language-users to achieve
distinctive purposes conducive to the quest for an ever more fully human and
uniquely personal existence. In the end,
however, I cannot allow any of these purposes to stifle my elusive longing for
ever-deepening intimacy with each Person in the triune God and with those I
love.
In short, given my intense longing to live
with personal integrity, I cannot submit to a second-level language designed to
accredit moral judgments or imperatives generated by a metaphor of power and
judgment. Those imperatives are voiced
by the cries of the oppressed, dispossessed, marginalized, silenced, outcast,
and even by barbarians outside the walls, while judgments are always informed
by a hidden will to power. And in my
everyday experience, I now see that such lapses are counter-productive,
self-destructive, and wounding to anyone who trusts me.
Since I analyze moral discourse from the
perspective offered by Wittgenstein's analysis of everyday languages, I revise
the metaphor which led philosophers in ancient Greece to privilege the
political over the personal dimensions of experience. Their metaphor envisioned the city as the
cradle and crucible of both culture and civilization. My revision envisions everyday language as
the cradle and crucible of moral discourse.
First and foremost, this language transmits a form of life which enables
language-users to transform a longing for intimacy into a realizable
quest. The realizability of the quest is
attested by all the tests which the implications of the metaphor of intimacy
successfully passed. But everyday
English also transmits forms of life indebted to the analyses of language and
experience generated by the metaphor of power and judgment, and these forms of
life also enable language-users to achieve distinctive purposes conducive to
the quest for an ever more fully human and uniquely personal existence. In the end, however, I cannot allow any of these
purposes to stifle my elusive longing for ever-deepening intimacy with each
Person in the triune God and with those I love.
In short, given my intense longing to live
with personal integrity, I cannot submit to a second-level language designed to
accredit moral judgments or imperatives generated by a metaphor of power and
judgment. Those imperatives are voiced
by the cries of the oppressed, dispossessed, marginalized, silenced, outcast,
and even by barbarians outside the walls, while judgments are always informed
by a hidden will to power. And in my
everyday experience, I now see that such lapses are counter-productive,
self-destructive, and wounding to anyone who trusts me.
No comments:
Post a Comment