Echoes of the "common good" can be
heard in the principle which functioned as the god-term in Bentham's utilitarianism. Bentham addressed issues raised by a
transition from the medieval belief that
God demanded conformity to a divinely ordained social order to an enthusiastic
embrace of the promise that the industrial system enabled human beings to harness
nature to their purposes. To deal with
the massive disruptions produced by an inexorably advancing industrialization
and the dehumanizing slums produced by an unrestrained exploitation of
individuals, Bentham posited the formula, "the greatest good of the
greatest number," as the god-term in a moral discourse designed to harness
the mastery over nature to social ends.
In effect, Bentham realized that the
competition which propelled the Industrial Revolution could result in a
Hobbesian war of all against all. In his
response, he wedded the metaphor of individuality forged by Locke to the
assumption that the industrial revolution was irreversible. Echoing the assumption that individuals act
out of enlightened self-interest, he re-centered moral discourse in a
disinterested calculus designed to distribute the goods produced by an emerging
capitalism as fairly as possible. And he
was willing to ground moral discourse in an economic system in which some would
inevitably be losers.
(NB:
Even a cursory analysis of the political discourse in the United States
reveals its debt to an amorphous utilitarianism. For the most part, Democrats act
pragmatically. On their part,
Republicans claim to work from principle, but the principles they advocate are
little more than rationalizations of policies designed to protect the
privileges of the wealthy and powerful.
They win advocates only as long as they are useful for the purpose that
rules the party.)
To
escape from a moral discourse which required some individuals to submit to
exploitation, John Stuart Mill presented utilitarianism as a vision, not a
calculus. As a young man, he had
suffered a breakdown which evoked in him an intense awareness of the personal
dimensions of experience. Later, as a
literary heir of the biblical tradition, he placed the notion of
"use" at the center of the prophetic vision which located God's moral
will in the cries of the oppressed, dispossessed, marginalized and silenced. In effect, he espoused a traditional moral
discourse designed to promote the quest for a fully human and uniquely personal
existence for all. And from that
cultural heritage, he envisioned a society which trusted that free individuals
would gladly use their abilities to the fullest. As a supplement to this inherently political
discourse, he also suggested that addressing the increasingly complex issues
generated by the Industrial Revolution would evoke the fullest use of anyone's
abilities.
Marx, in turn, echoed Mill's vision in his
vision of a society governed by the formula:
"From each according to his abilities; to each according to his
needs." During the decades
dominated by the Cold War, Marx's use of Mill was the kiss of death for Mill's
critique of utilitarianism from within.
I find that very sad.
Lest I go on endlessly, I merely note that
an ethics of intimacy renders moral discourses centered in various versions of
the common good irrelevant by centering political discourse in a shared
vulnerability, not a struggle for power.
In this context, no one can pretend to offer an authoritative definition
of what constitutes the "common good."
No comments:
Post a Comment