Wednesday, December 30, 2015

43. REASON REVISITED


    Aquinas provides a prime example of a theologian who failed to realize the implications of the supposition that human beings are rational animals.  Thus, in his use of the medieval metaphor of the Two Books, Aquinas assumed that an autonomous Book of Nature authored by a rational and purposive Creator could be read by "the natural light of reason."  In so doing, he was blithely unaware that he endowed a literary construct with the power to compel assent to descriptive formulations and consent to moral judgments which satisfy its dictates.

     From a postmodernist perspective, however, this construct was clearly designed to resolve issues raised by the interiorization of the detachment inherent in reading and writing as an interrogatory stance.  The central issue: because an interrogatory stance licenses endless questioning, it posits an empty literary space whose hollow center can be filled by communications which reduce dialogue to a meaningless babble or by rhetorics centered in the dictum, "Might makes right."  As the product of a literary tradition, it is hardly natural.


      Historically, the hollow center of the interrogatory stance was filled in different ways by the Hellenic and Hebrew literary traditions.  The ancient Greeks filled the center with a metaphorical One which wedded (1) the totalizing thrust of languages governed by the logic of continuous prose and (2) the model of an enduring, bounded, changeless text written in continuous prose.  In marked contrast, to process Israel's historical experience, the ancient Hebrews forged a literary form whose narrative structure guaranteed that any story could be endlessly retold in ways that reveal that human history is an open-ended process which cannot be consigned to a single text written in the past or present.

      Evidence of the rule of the One over the Hellenic literary tradition can be found in distinctions which emerged once literary languages took on lives of their own.  For our present purposes, two such distinctions are particularly significant.  One, as texts replaced memory as the repository of the past, philosophers (and dramatists) were able to use an awareness of how the present differed from the past to envision future states of affairs to be produced through human agency.  Two, literary works provided a detached perspective on the interplay among the workings of everyday languages, the flux of experience, and the different ways that cultures carved up reality.  In this context, the One promised to transform endless questioning into focused inquiries which enabled mute nature to answer well-formed questions.  More importantly, an intertextual dialogue among the pre-Socratics, Plato and Aristotle fostered the supposition that reason was needed to govern unruly and disruptive passions and desires.  As a result, ethical analyses of moral discourse gradually replaced the use of tragedies and comedies to process the everyday experiences of life in emerging city-states.  Presumably, the rule of the One could yield definitive judgments which imposed closure on endless questioning and thereby precluded lapses into arbitrariness, conventionality or the will to power celebrated by the dictum, "Might makes right."

    Quite obviously, any detached perspective operates on a second level.  In this context, Logic, a language about language, decreed that analyses of the workings of everyday languages must be generated and governed by a logical principle of identity (or a principle of non-contradiction).  Quite obviously, this principle privileges the totalizing thrust of language.  (In the twentieth century, the rule of the One became suspect when efforts to formulate an ideal language revealed the impossibility of constructing a purely formal framework for analyses of language and experience which would yield a comprehensive and complete language capable of revealing the workings of nature transparently.)

    With regard to the enduring reality underlying the flux of experience, Plato and Aristotle provided competing visions.  Plato's seminal works grounded everyday language in a timeless realm of interpenetrating Ideal Forms, while Aristotle's appropriation of Plato simply implanted these forms in a conception of the potency of prime matter bounded by a finite universe.  And in this context, Aristotle wove the idealist and naturalist conventions into a correspondence theory of truth which promised that analyses of everyday experiences generated and governed by reason would ultimately provide an ideal language which revealed the whole of reality transparently, in depth and detail. 

    Here, I simply note that both philosophy and theology are second-level disciplines.  From this perspective, Aquinas' frequent references to "the natural light of reason" can serve as a paradigm example of the philosophical tradition's uncritical acceptance of the authority of reason.  On a broader canvas, Aquinas made no secret of his desire to wed philosophy and theology forever in a hierarchical framework which depicted philosophy as the handmaiden of theology.  To legitimate his willingness to baptize Aristotle as the Philosopher, he inscribed the rule of reason in the conception of a rational and purposive Creator who authored an autonomous Book of Nature and supplemented this god-term with the assumption that human beings made in the image of their Creator were rational animals.  And from these assumptions, he proceeded to forge a constrictive belief-system which, not surprisingly, continues to evoke frantic efforts to save the authority of Aquinas from the postmodernist resurgence of the interrogatory stance.


     In effect, the interplay between an interiorized interrogatory stance and the totalizing thrust of the logic of continuous prose ensures that, whenever one dominates, reason will recoil upon itself.  Descartes' transformation of the interrogatory stance into a methodical doubt provides a clear example.  To introduce this method, Descartes described constrictive medieval belief-systems as edifices erected on sand.  To clothe the method with the mantle of authority, he filled the hollow center of the interrogatory stance with a narrative structure designed to provide a certain starting point for inquiries capable of yielding definitive judgments.  As a narrative, this starting point functioned as a myth of pure beginnings.  But the myth merely re-centered the rule of the One in an abstract conception of solipsistic thinking beings.

    In fact, the rule of the One was already present in Descartes' awareness that he needed an ontological argument for the existence of a Creator of all else to support his insistence that the autonomous Book of Nature was written in the language of mathematics. the existence of an infinite Creator of all else.  As a perspective, the rule of the One played both sides of the street.  As an interrogatory stance, it generated the "Cartesian chasm" between subjectivity and objectivity which, in turn, implied that solipsistic individuals faced one another as the Other.  But as the voice of thinking beings, it inscribed vestiges of the traditional privileging of the universal over the individuals in the assumption that thinking beings could occupy a detached, disinterested, dispassionate, god-like perspective interchangeably.  (The rule of the One reappears in this notion of interchangeability.)

    Today, the hermeneutics of suspicion which propels the postmodernist movement is a hybrid which fills the hollow center of the conception of solipsistic thinking beings with Nietzsche's exposure of the ways that rationalism disguises a will to power.  To expose the operation of this hidden will to power, this hermeneutical theory encodes a critical apparatus which shows (1) that, far from conferring on individuals the power to escape entirely from the formative power of everyday languages, these languages are repositories of violence and (2) that no critical apparatus can eliminate prejudice, conventionality and the operation of disguised wills to power.

    To present themselves as literary heirs of traditional liberation movements, postmodernist critics insist that a hermeneutics designed to translate the interrogatory stance into a stance of suspicion is liberating without re-introducing god-terms designed to authorize judgments of any sort.  In effect, they respect the contributions of the rule of the One to the development of language over the centuries, yet refuse to re-inscribe a Cartesian subjectivity in a version of the conception of the autonomous individual which functions as the god-term in the myth of Modernity.  As a result, they offer readings of (1) texts, (2) languages indebted to literary traditions, and (3) everyday experiences textured by these languages which extend a relentless critique of the authority of reason to a subversion of authority in any shape or form.  And in so doing, it supplements Nietzsche proclamation of the "death of God" with its own proclamation of the "death of the author."

    As a literary heir of the western philosophical tradition, however, the postmodernist movement exploits the empty literary space projected by the Babylonian epics consigned to writing in the second millennium, BCE.  And the will to power of its adherents is quite evident in the fact that they can only fill the hollow center of this space with a hollow voice of prophetic protest against the violence enshrined in the distinctions and boundaries which are foundational to the depiction of human existence implicit in the political, economic and religious rhetorics which are allowed to frame moral issues uncritically in the United States today.

     In this vein, the gurus whose texts gave shape and form to an otherwise amorphous movement pretend that their protests against enshrined violence not only wrest the mantle of prophecy from Nietzsche, but also justify their self-presentations as prophets of a movement of liberation.  On my part, however, I find that Wittgenstein's analysis of the workings of language is far more fruitful than those offered by Derrida, in particular.  Recognizing the collapse of efforts to delineate an ideal language capable of presenting reality transparently, Wittgenstein replaced his earlier fascination with the assumption that language is a formal system with the thesis that everyday languages transmit many forms of life, each designed to realize a distinct human purpose, rather than a vision designed to legitimate definitive descriptive and moral judgments.

    Wittgenstein's insight enables me to re-read the readings generated by a hermeneutics of suspicion with suspicion.  On the one hand, it reveals forms of life capable of authorizing truly prophetic protests against the violence legitimated by everyday language, but derive them from forms of life which are conducive to the quest for a fully human and uniquely personal existence.  As such, it, too, can function as a voice of liberation.  And the perspective it offers leads me to suspect that those who espouse the reading strategies encoded in a hermeneutics of suspicion seek to liberate themselves from the need to explore the prophetic calls inscribed in the metaphors of intimacy projected by Israel's great prophets.

    In effect, I suggest that the hermeneutics of suspicion liberates postmodernist readers from the demands of a literary tradition centered in the search for a language capable of translating an elusive longing for a more fully human and uniquely personal existence into a realizable quest.  Presumably, the pretense that this reading code enables them to speak anonymously absolves them of the need for vulnerable self-revelations which would enable them to voice their protests against violence in their own voices.  If so, they ignore the distinction between liberation from [sic] and liberation that proponents of contract-theories of society must respect.





No comments:

Post a Comment