As
the bearer of the ideals of the Enlightenment, the myth of Modernity presents
autonomous individuals as creators of their own unique identities, masters of
the universe through the knowledge provided by scientific advances, co-authors
of ideal societies, lords of history, and arbiters of their own destiny.
As a literary construct, it interweaves
idealist conventions forged by Plato, Aquinas' formulaic depiction of God, the
myth of pure beginnings generated by Descartes' methodical doubt, Rousseau's
romantic insistence that human beings are made unique, free and creative by
nature rather than by God, and Kant's abstract conception of the autonomous
individual who is the sole author of the text which inscribes his
autobiography.
The role of conventions derived from
Plato's realm of Ideal Forms is particularly evident in the confidence that
reasonable beings will co-author a social contract capable of constituting an
ideal society.
The appropriation of Aquinas' depiction of
God is equally obvious. In his Summa Theologica, Aquinas presented God
as a rational and purposive Creator of unique individuals who shared a universal
human nature, the master of the universe, the author of a hierarchically
structured social order, the lord of history, and the arbiter of human
destiny. To lend authority to their
myth, Enlightenment authors simply replaced this abstract conception of God
with Kant's equally abstract conception of the autonomous individual.
To counter the traditional belief that God
is active in human history, the myth placed autonomous individuals in a
primordial state encoded in Descartes' myth of pure beginnings. As Sartre's articulation of the human journey
into the unknown dramatized, individuals who entered each moment of the journey
of life as a pure beginning not only could, but had to create the sort of
unique identities celebrated by a Rousseauean romanticism. And since the replacement of God by
autonomous individuals was seemingly accredited by the way that scientific
advances conferred the ability to harness nature to human purposes, the
equation of scientific knowledge and power by Roger Bacon accredited the belief
that autonomous individuals were masters of the universe.
The appropriation of the depiction of God
as the Lord of history was more complicated.
Histories written by human beings are narratives designed to integrate
the experience of memorable events in a coherent vision. In this context, idealist conventions derived
from Plato's posit were to legitimate ideologies which decreed that history
moved, inexorably, toward a determinate end.
(Paradigm examples of this dubious argument
can be found in the works of Hegel and Marx.
Marx forged a hermeneutical theory capable of standing Hegel on his head
because it revealed that the course of history was propelled by a dialectical
structured matter. With this peculiar
conception of matter as his god-term, Marx developed a vision which defined the
end of history as an ideal society governed by a single principle, "From
each according to his abilities; to each
according to his needs." And since
history is the record of conflict among individuals, history would come to an
end in an enduring state of eternal bliss.)
At the dawn of the twentieth century,
however, intellectuals who expected an imminent fulfillment of the promises of
the myth of Modernity were profoundly disillusioned by World War I, a war to
end all wars, and, in the following decades, by the eruption of World War II
triggered by Hitler's seductive ideology and especially by the Holocaust. To process this experience, Kafka and Beckett
composed seminal texts which voiced this disillusionment long before
philosophers became aware of the sterility of a myth which celebrated the
autonomous individual and the workings of a detached, dispassionate voice of
reason. On this literary stage, however,
Nietzsche's insistence that his exposure of the cultural relativity of
prevailing moral discourses revealed the working of an all-pervasive will to
power forced intellectuals to recognize that the celebration of personal
autonomy deprived their protests against random eruptions of violence and
concentrations of power in impersonally operating institutions of any semblance
of moral authority.
Decades later, adherents of the
postmodernist movement exploited the fear that a moral discourse which promised
a more fully human and uniquely personal existence could at best generate yet
another -ism. To expose the will to
power inherent in judgments of any sort, the gurus of the movement entered an
arena framed by the Protestant tendency to encode protests in slogans. In this context, because the Protestant
slogan, "sola Scriptura",
invoked the conception of an autonomous text, it provided an easy target. In effect, these critics used Nietzsche's
slogan, "God is dead", to sound the death-knell for belief-systems,
ideologies and theories centered in a god-term.
And from this starting point, they expanded their critique to include
the authority accorded to the texts which had acquired canonical status in
literature, philosophy and theology. In
the process, they added Barthes' announcement of the "death of the
author" to Nietzsche's slogan, "God is dead."
From my perspective, Nietzsche's slogan
sounded a long overdue death-knell for Aquinas' baptism of Aristotelian
metaphysics as the framework for theological inquiries concerning a
relationship between grace and nature.
At the dawn of the Modern Era, Descartes' geometrization of the universe
replaced the hierarchical and teleological structure of Aristotelian
metaphysics with an empty literary space.
Without the need for added commentary, this revolutionary revision
exposed the anthropomorphism inherent in the belief that a rational God had to
inscribe his moral purpose in a teleologically structured Book of Nature. And since my introduction to the philosophy
of science had led me to welcome Nietzsche's proclamation of the death of
Aquinas' conception of God for some time, I was far more intrigued by a slogan
which sounded the death knell of Kant's conception of autonomous individuals
who could author the stories of their lives in splendid isolation.
From
a critical perspective, I agree with the insistence (1) that everyday languages
exert a formative power on longings, passions, desires, perceptions,
imagination, thought, motives, intentions and aspirations and (2) that a
fictive voice of reason cannot provide a detached, god-like perspective on the
interplay among language, experience and reality capable of liberating
reasonable beings from that formative power in a way that allows a pure
beginning. As a result, I agree with the
postmodernist deconstructions of the use of metaphors of individuality
generated by Descartes' methodical doubt which converged in Kant's effort to
ground moral discourse in an abstract conception of an autonomous individual. Indeed, working backwards from a moral
discourse generated by a metaphor of intimacy, I agree with the postmodernist
subversion of each of the five promises of the myth of Modernity.
I.e., experience has taught me that I am
not and cannot be the sole creator of my personal identity. But it has also taught me that fidelity to
committed involvements which invite me to co-author a single story of a shared
journey into the unknown evokes vulnerable self-revelations in which I speak in
my own voice. To discern the hold of the
will to power enshrined in everyday English, I welcome the critical apparatus
encoded in the hermeneutics of suspicion, but I cannot allow it to subvert
repeated efforts to speak in my own voice.
Paradoxically, to speak in my own voice, I must not pretend that I have
the authority to impose my judgments and agendas on others. But if my vulnerable self-revelation speaks
as a life-giving voice, it will speak for itself to those who are willing to
listen.
No comments:
Post a Comment